Axioms or circularity - By Martin Prior

Axioms or circularity
When I was at primary school I had a special dictionary for schools and I wanted to find the meaning of a word A.  Well the dictionary told me it meant B.  But what did B mean?  Well the dictionary said that B meant A.  So I asked my parents and they were most irritated and clearly felt I should show more initiative.  Deadlock.
In an earlier Issue I argued that the purpose of life is love but that the purpose of love is life, so that anyone seeking the purpose of life would simply go round in circles:
 

Well, this won’t do for argumentation, and we have heard the accusation that certain arguments are circular.  Thus some people will say that abortion is murder.  So how do you define murder?  Oh, to include abortion.  We are in fact on a better path if we say that life is sacred, since as long as you can define life - i.e. what is the meaning of ‘life’ as opposed to what is the meaning of life – then you are on firmer ground, but nobody can argue with you.

So in logic, one builds on axioms, things we take as given.  In fact I myself spent 20 years of my life working as a statistician.  And within the various argumentations of statistics, one thing is left undefined, and that is probability itself.  Or at least that was the case nearly 50 years ago when I first studied statistics.  Such undefined  items are known as ‘primitives’.

We may note that relatable to axioms are theorems: propositions that may be proved from axioms (and/or existing theorems) .  Now if I have a formula containing expressions such as  (a+b), ab, (a Ù b), etc, we have a principle of uniform substitutability.  Because all of these operators are commutative, we can replace them with their ‘back-to-front’, i.e. commute them.  We may do this in a system which has an axiom or theorem of the form  (a.b) = (b.a), but we must do so consistently.

Another rule is that if we know (i) that A is always true, and (ii) A implies B, then B must always be true.  This is the rule of Detachment (or in Latin Modus Ponens).  Some logicians do without this rule.

Now all logicians agree that when proving things, one must build up axioms from ‘primitives’ and definitions.  One usually has two primitives, such as ‘not’ and ‘or’.  This was the starting point of Bertrand Russell and P.H. Whitehead in their Principia Mathematica.  Mordechaj Wajsberg on the other hand, produced several systems including one in which implication and falsity were taken as primitive.

But let us tabulate all this:

 
Tarski, Bernays, and Wajsberg, ‘basis 1’, 1937

Note that axioms may be built up depending on how many variables or separate propositions they involve: if an axiom involves one variable, generally you cannot say anything about a proposition with two variables, etc. 

But maybe we have a circularity here as well: for logic you have to turn to philosophy for its axioms and ‘primitives’.  Look at that primitive falsehood!  But philosophy cannot proceed without being logical!

By Martin Prior

References

Hackstaff, L.H. (1966)  Systems of Formal Logic. D. Reidel Publishing, 1966.

Wajsberg, Mordechaj (1937-9) “Metalogische Beiträge”  In: Wiadomości Matematyczne Volumes 43 (1937) and 47 (1939), translated by McCall and (partly) P. Woodruff  in Contributions to Metalogic (1967).

Whitehead, Alfred North and Bertrand Russell (1910)  Principia Mathematica.  Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.


The Philosophy Takeaway 'Open Topic' Issue 33

Want to write for us?

If you would like to submit an article for consideration, please contact thephilosophytakeaway@gmail.com

Search This Blog